Sunday, 31 January 2010

Speculative Realism Reading Group: Nihilism Rebound


Well, we had a great reading group session last Wednesday. We read Ray Brassier’s Nihil Unbound. This is a quite a dense text, but we had a lot of fun unpacking it. Ray Brassier’s main endeavour in this text is, as he claims, to bring the purview of the sciences within the ontological remit of philosophy. For Brassier, there has been a sundering of this dichotomy, especially within 20th Century Philosophy. In opposition, Brassier wants to provide a speculative and metaphysical grammar which holds for both sciences and philosophy; in short to give provides the underlying language for an account of ‘human meaning’. Brassier’s primary thesis is obscure and hard to articulate, however, it does provide a radical departure for the trajectory of European Philosophy. Brassier wants to argue for a new form of nihilism. One that aggregates the nothingness of all entities, hence, nihil unbound. In a way, he is continuing on from some of the insights of Meillassoux who endorses the contingency of all entities. In Chapter 1 Brassier begins by following the insights of Wilfred Sellars who opposed the manifest image of the human from the scientific image of the human. The manifest image suggests that there is a realm of human self-perception or human life. The scientific image suggests that humans are generated out of complex physical phenomenon. Brassier sides with the latter, insisting that we can attain an objective perspective on our own subjectivity; Brassier also uses Paul Churchland’s eliminative materialism to buttress his claims, who for him, has a more sophisticated account of phenomenal appearance in material terms.

We looked at chapter 3 of the text, which took up Brassier’s relationship to Meillassoux. Meillassoux’s as we saw in the last reading group, suggests that philosophy especially that of the Kantian and Post-Kantian variety, suggests that humans are the centre of all representation. Basically there can be no access to reality without it going through human perception, transcendental apperception and synthetic a priori and so forth. The task in turn is to think how we can think of reality in itself without any constituting activity of human subjectivity. Brassier repeats Meillassoux’s argument about the arche-fossil, the arche-fossil is roughly a phenomena we know which exists prior to human access. It is millions of years old and we know this exists thanks to scientific evidence. The significance of the arche-fossil is that it points to a ‘cognizable’ experience exterior to the existence of subjectivity. These events are events prior to both life and thought. Human consciousness itself is limited and finite. There is therefore a region of existence that is not dependent on human consciousness. The existence of phenomena transcends these limitations.

As the arche-fossil shows, there are innumerable phenomena in existence that are not dependent on humans. As relevant to philosophy are the surface of alpha centurai and the time of the origin of life over 10 billion years ago. It is also worth noting that all this applies to pretty much all of contemporary continental philosophy: Wittgenstein, Heidegger, Husserl and post-structuralism. In Brassier words, all these schools of philosophy surreptitiously find ways of keeping the non-manifest within the manifest image. To reconcile the ‘manifest’ and the ‘scientific image’ it is necessary to think how cognizable events can think the reality of the universe without relying on the apparatus of cognitive events. This is the task which Brassier sets himself.

In constructing his positive philosophy, Brassier asks us to look at the arche-fossil. The arche-fossil indicates that there exists a time prior to the time of human manifestation. Human time is based on events, past, present and future. It is based on the flow of succession. I think the kernel of Brassier’s work is in some way to try and show how this more originary time generates subjective time. If we can think this we can think Being qua Being. Subjective time is always therefore the effect of more originary time with human subjectivity being only an individuation of it. Conceptualizing this originary time as the foundation of subjectivity allows Brassier to present an axiomatic foundation to thought which is not generated by thought itself. Because ancestral time or the arche-fossil time is prior to subjective time it must in some way condition the coming into existence of perceptual or apparent time. Brassier at this point forces the issue; his account forgoes the modern and rational account of philosophy as a modern ground of subjectivity, as well as the pre-modern cosmological hierarchy of being. There is neither subject nor object in themselves and neither are these notions sustainable in an infinite and immortal enduring substance.

Brassier develops this line of thought in his chapter on Deleuze. This is one of the stronger chapters in the book, and is well worth attention. It is here that he works out what he has previously called the isomorphy of thought and being. While I can’t go into this in detail, I will mention some points. There is an interesting counterpoints here between Deleuze and Heidegger; two major but ultimately unfulfilled vectors of 20th Century thought. Deleuze remains too vitalistic. His work, although important, fails to embrace the region of the inanimate and still remains too focused on ‘life’ philosophy. In a way Deleuze fails to embrace death. Heidegger remains too focused on death, or human finitude. It is for Heidegger death that makes a human exceptional, and mitigates the human from being reduced to one thing among others in the world. The role of death for Heidegger, as that which constitutes Dasein, is that which stops the human from being another thing in the world. Death stops the human being ontic. The two great philosophers of life and death don’t go far enough. Heidegger doesn’t wholly restrict questions of temporality to human Dasein, but ultimately fails to conceive in any detailed the temporality on absolute time. Brassier also is not keen on Heidegger’s distinction between life and the sciences.



There is thus only a localised or limited form of negation in Heidegger. It is restricted to human life. It also presupposes a distinction between human lived life and biological life. To this he opposes Deleuze’s notion of ‘time in itself’. Being itself is understood as temporal differentiation. The Bergson lineage is evident albeit amended. Being is univocal and there it is where “Deleuze rehabilitates the thesis of ontological univocity such that it is being qua time that is ‘said in one and the same sense of all its individuating differences or intrinsic modalities.” (162)As mentioned above, Being is explainable in terms of its self-generation, where all differences are an effect of this one process. Change is part of negation, and what he wants is the pure negation of being itself, not, that of human being. To put it quickly, on the plus side Deleuze has a radical and unified notion of death. So rather than death being human, it constitutes all of being. There is an originary metamorphosis in being itself. Deleuze surpasses Nietzsche‘s nihilism who remains caught between the need for a stable and false appearance and a realm of being as pure becoming. Becoming is dependent on creatures who are capable of evaluating it as such. Only beings who can come to terms with will to power can conceive of it in terms of joyous affirmation or resentful negation or ressentiment. So the correlationism still stands.

Brassier prefers the more radical thesis that dichotomy between affirmation and nothingness is a false dichotomy. Instead we should only have nothingness itself.
So Brassier’s point is that there is always a time prior to any event or entity which causes ultimately negates any self-sufficiency of these objects. There is destructibility; therefore there must be a nihilation. This form of time is pure. It does not pass or cease or is not constituted by death in any way. While Brassier does not explicitly say so, his metaphysics remains strangely immortal. I think this is because his originary time is in some way Deleuzian. It is a pure and monistic form of time that is conceived as an eternal self-generation absolutely immanent to itself. There can be only one, which has scalar degrees of differentiation generated out of this one being. There is I think here a danger that Brassier repeats the temporal succession of consciousness on a cosmic level. Originary time is not susceptible to change because it is pure and empty. It is the eternal becoming of one monistic being. He calls this the pure and empty form of time. Pure I take it means that this form of time is uncontaminable, empty I take it to mean that which is a void that cannot be filled. Either way the nothingness that Brassier endorses, seems immune to particular and specific objects and worlds coming to be. It is difficult to negotiate notions of anteriority and posteriority; however, put in this way, it is hard to see anything happening at all let alone nothing. To think of an originary time, the pure and empty form of time is not possible tout court since nothingness itself cannot happen or be an event. This is not at all because, or restricted to the limitations of human consciousness. To adopt notions of becoming, whether monistic are not is to adopt temporal and relational terms which only allow something to be cognizable within spatio-temporal coordinates. Some questions need to be answered how does such a nothingness have an efficacy or operational modality.

For Brassier, the important thing is take up the trajectory of pure nothingness. It is to think eternal nothingness, a pure eternity of the nothingness of all things. Once we achieve this then we can grasp the truth of all being i.e. the nothingness that is writ into all entities. If we have this, we can surpass we can surpass limitations and think of the cosmos as unbound. Hence, nihil unbound. There are no limits to which nothingness can apply itself to. Eternal and Becoming at the same time. This eternity is basically for Brassier the great leveller. It is the truth of all things. To understand this allows us to have in Brassier’s words, an ‘isomorphy of thinking and being’. This seems to be the nub of his ideas. If we can get rid of passing and change, and demarcations and qualifications, therefore we can get to the eternal nothing, or the eternal becoming nothing of beings. Then we have something pure and empty without structural traces or relationality. If we have this, we have an isomorphy of the material of thinking and being.

I do have some reservations here in terms of consistency. Brassier endorses the enduringness of nothingness rather than something. There is a tension here that I think is difficult to overcome. If one is to acknowledge an anterior time to cognitive time, then I don’t see how it is possible to think of this without some temporal and spatial relationality. Time and space are not exclusive to human consciousness; it is not as if the human mind owns these or constitutes the nature of reality. In fact the only way one could claim this, is if one buys into the Kantian notion of consciousness in the first. One interesting point that Neil raised in this light in the reading group, is that Brassier wilfully presents the demonic level of nothingness. The exact obverse of the reason why there is something rather than nothing. Now, the reason there is something rather than nothing is because of nothingness. In all of this we did think that there was a strong theological trace in Brassier’s work. The pure and empty form of nothingness does have some kind of immortal and God like structure. It is something that can transcend death and survives and remains strangely resilient to the death of all things in the universe.

There are some interesting and creative moments towards the end of the book. It turns to Lyotard’s dramatic moment in The Inhuman. Being itself will ultimately become extinct with the extinguishing power of the sun in 4.8 billion years. The absolute telos of all is absolute pure nothingness, it is nothing but negation. Telos is indeed wholly the wrong word to use. It is just that writ into our existence is, as Brassier puts it, the fact that everything is dead already. For Brassier, this is not something that will happen. It is happening already. There is a trace of the stellar death which wipes out all human horizons and which is written in to the earth’s history and future on grand scale; Brassier presents a view of existence that is much more dramatic than Heidegger’s Dasein and the finitude of death or any Sartrian bifurcation of Being and nothingness. The point is that the sun is dying. We know this from science just as humans are dying. We are also aware of the heat death of the universe. In an odd way Brassier’s work is bookended by materialist beginning and ends of the arche-fossil and heat death of the universe. If one presents a short summary of Brassier, it could be seen as a superimposing of existentialism on the entire universe. It is cosmic absurdity without humanity. While the sun cannot become anxious in the sense that humans do, it can certainly die and have a relationship to change. This is what he calls the death of death; the death of the centrality of the mortal and the human: the unbinding of nihilism itself.

The heat death of the universe will announce the death of all matter and eternal darkness. There is no immortality. There is no transmigration of souls. There is no relative survival. One cannot transport between brains and machines. All this does is borrow time, literally, all events and objects share in this extinction of the universe. What things are, what they will become are forever negated or negatable. Language, Dasein, embodiment mask this truth existence all of these and hide the truth of the cosmos essential nihilation. One could posit a curious reversal of Derrida here, the trace of negation is futural and from the past. The arche fossil indicates our prior nihilation and the heat death of the universe indicates our futural nihilation. By reversing Derrida, Brassier is a prophet of nihilation rather than the messianic. There is always a trace of negation from the future and past. This is however configured as extinction and it is something that operates actively. It has an efficacy. It motivates and conditions all things. It is beyond possibility, it is beyond temporality. It commands and usurps the sovereignty of all entities and remains the eternal destiny of all things that come to be. In an interesting move Brassier couches this in Levinasian terms. Extinction is the other of natural science rather than the other of the human and the sovereignty of consciousness which Levinas endorses. The other is seen in Levinasian terms as a ‘wounding or haemorrhaging’ of all subjectivity. Extinction performs a similar function. Behind all appearances is an anonymous and restless being or Levinas’ ‘il y a'. It is the anonymity of death that is at hand in all things. While for Levinas the Other was the trace of God, for Brassier it is the trace of extinction. The proximity of these notions is thought provoking. Levinas god is infinite and unbreakable, the anonymous rustling of the infinity of absolute immanence. The notion of an empty, anonymous and unbreakable nothingness may thus not be as resolutely entrenched in scientific materialism as Brassier might allow. However, read as is, with the appropriation of Levinas Brassier has overturned theology. It is the trace of extinction that rules out all possibilities not the trace of God. Thought has to become equal to this task of negativity. It has to become one with it.

Patrick O'Connor

Thursday, 31 December 2009

Neil Turnbull will be speaking at the 2010 Telos confernece

The 2010 TELOS Conference

January 16, 2010
New York City

From Lifeworld to Biopolitics: Empire in the Age of Obama

In the context of a dramatic reorganization of the relationships among state, market, and society, the 2010 Telos Conference will turn its attention to competing accounts, both theoretical and empirical, of the new modalities of administration, domination, and power. Facing the authoritarian state and a politicized market, how does one “defend society”? Has the strong state and a repoliticization of society returned in the name of left populism in the United States? How does international power operate in new forms of empire? How will Obama’s foreign policy and the economic crisis affect the structure of global relations?

The conference will address the extension of politicized control into ever greater realms of social life. What theoretical tools are available? How can we trace the process historically? Classical Critical Theory of the mid-twentieth century described a “totally administered society” in which an elaborate bureaucracy combined with a “culture industry” in order to eliminate spontaneity. Yet some viewed the era of deregulation (and the paradigms of postmodernism) as a rollback of administration and homogeneity. Do we now face the return to the strong state and a repoliticization of society in the name of left populism in the United States? Or has it been the transition from the old mass media to the Internet that has reshaped the dynamic of politics and culture?

Meanwhile, the brief moment of a presumed single superpower and unilateralism is shading into an international disorder of multiple power conflicts among strong states, no longer confronted with human rights expectations or a democratization agenda. The resurgent control of society has taken on global proportions: China, Russia, North Korea, Iran, and Venezuela. How does international power operate in new forms of empire? Have “military-industrial complexes” been replaced by cultural hegemonies, defined by the spread of languages and religions? Do developments such as political Islam or Chinese nationalism indicate that “society” has been the hidden driver of state power all along? What about the shared “liberal” and “realistic” assumption that economic liberalization will produce political opening and democratization? Has state capitalism in the East responded better to the global economic crisis than market capitalism in the West?

Conference Registration Fee: $115, which includes a one-year subscription to Telos. For current holders of individual subscriptions to Telos, the registration fee is $55. Please add $50 to the registration fee if you will be joining us at the conference dinner. To register, visit us at www.telospress.com.

Monday, 14 December 2009

Patrick's Top 6 Books of 2009


Ok, everybody. Seeing as it’s the time of year for lists and ‘best-ofs’ etc. and all types of E4 and Channel 4 hackery I thought I would add my tuppence to the pence. Below are the top three books that influenced me most this year. You might find some of them interesting and some of them not so interesting. Of the books I have read here, I think the following made the most impression on me. Unfortunately, I didn’t get through many novels this year, which is a shame. If I did this last year, I think it would have been a Nabokov only top 6!!!

1. G.W. Leibniz – Philosophical Essays, trans. Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber, Cambridge, IN: Hackett, 1989.

OK, to me Leibniz is one of the most underrated of all philosophers. For me at least, he would probably edge out Nietzsche and come a close second behind Hegel in an all time list. He was probably one of the last universal geniuses we had. As well as being a philosopher of note, he was a diplomat, mathematician, inventor of the calculus, engineer, technological innovator, inventor of binary, and if only for the lack of technology quite possibly would have invented the computer (Look up the ‘Stepped Reckoner’which was and is a mechanical calculating machine!!! ), and general all round polymath. This collection is just brilliant; it contains the ‘Discourse on Metaphysics’ as well as the ‘Monadology’. You can learn tonnes about Metaphysics by reading any of the essays here, and also many of the essays are short if dense. Also much of his texts are in the form of letters which are quite dramatic once you get into them. On many an occasion Leibniz is downright insulting. It is worth looking at his letter to Queen Sophie of Prussia where he patiently explains the history of philosophy to her, in as basic terms as he can muster, through gritted teeth. I guess what I found valuable about Leibniz is that he presents a Metaphysics that can be construed in a radical light. Much has been made in the academy of the critique of metaphysics in recent years, that metaphysics is a dead end, that it is only ever a static enterprise, that it arrests the flux of the world and differences. In no way can one make this claim with Leibniz. Like Heidegger, metaphysics is a much more radicalized affair; Leibniz’s system presents a dynamic and active realization of the nature of reality. He allows us to ask the most traditional philosophical questions - what does it mean to be human, what is reality, what is the nature of existence – in the most radical and innovative way. Highlights in this text for me were his account of force and its relation to inertia. While most people get hung up on Leibniz’s theodicy and his justification of God and this as the best of all possible world, for me these would not be possible without the dynamic of force and inertia between monads. This is something often overlooked in historical summaries of Leibniz’s place in philosophy. Another highlight is Leibniz's meditations on the relativity of space, time and objects. What is most attractive for me is that Leibniz is such an imaginative philosopher; he forces you along with his journey. Reading Leibniz is just downright trippy at times; he places a huge demand on the reader to get a sense of his whole system is discernible in the minutest part. In short, how every monad potentially contains the entire universe!

2. John Milton: Paradise Lost, Harmondsworth, 1996.

It is always dangerous talking about Milton without skirting the danger of going into cliché about rebels and existential angst. While Milton’s Lucifer is certainly a proto-genitor for the tortured existential hero railing against all odds there is so much more to this rich text. Anyway, what I can say in a few words hopelessly fails to do justice to the richness of Paradise Lost. What I took from this stunning work was Lucifer as the essential figure of the human; brooding and vain, stuck somewhere between a desire to be human and a desire to be God. In an odd way, Milton makes humanity the hero of the text. Lucifer knows he will lose his fight with God, but getting his claws and a stake in human beings will alleviate the pain of hell. Nothing is worse than hell after all. The human therefore is his end; it is what gives his existence purpose, in a sense what he aspires to, something lesser than the Gods. For this reason the human is seen as a cosmic battle ground of good and evil. It is never a case of a clear demarcation of the two for Milton. There are no binary opposites here. The human is caught between the stars and the dirt. Milton dialectically presents the best and worst of humanity: a being with a foot in both camps and a home in neither. Milton’s work presents a meditation on the capacity and futility of man’s ambitions at one and the same time. The notion of fruit at the core of this poem presents us with the definitive metaphor of the human condition. Fruit, fruition, power, capacity; these notions, what they achieve and what they fail to achieve, are the heart of any human endeavour. This is why ‘fruit’ is so omnipresent in the arts from poetry, art and drama; fruit presents the perfect metaphor of decay, growth and flourishing and beauty and achievement at one and the same time. Satan’s advises Eve to eat the apple which sets in motion the necessity of human development. Right at human’s inception is a play between freedom and necessity. Without this, humans would not be what we are, we would remain reposed and comfortable in the Garden of Eden without struggle or challenge, safe and harmonious; a mere adornment to the divine. This is Satan’s paradoxical logic, by getting Eve to eat the apple, it opens us to the possibility of challenge and struggle and the attendant wisdom that comes with such experience. Without eating the apple, we would never have grown, we would never reach maturity nor would we ever recognize the limits of our ambitions. Correlatively, Satan is both Sophist and Philosopher at once. Without challenge and struggle we would never reach any form of wisdom about the world, we would only remain in a state of innocence, conversely without keeping ourselves in question and maintaining a sceptical stance to our wisdom we would only revert to an ignorance masquerading as innocence. Other highlights of Paradise Lost include Satan’s speech convincing the populace of hell to rise up once more after their defeat; never a finer sophistic oration will you get in the history of literature. Another highlight would be Milton’s presentation of the irreducible tension, jealousies, insecurities and class war between demons, angels in their relevant hierarchies. One of the most striking scenes is when Satan gets on the archangel Gabriel’s goat, by accusing him for being no more than an obsequious and servile middle manager. I know Milton will never be taken for a feminist but Eve’s eating of the apple, well what can you say, only ‘Good for her’! Milton’s Satan does us the service of showing us truly what we are, caught between the divine and the dirt, between Heaven and Hell.

3. Lucretius: On the Nature of the Universe, trans. Ronald Melville, Oxford: Oxford U.P., 1997

I think this is also a bit of a neglected gem. Although I think Deleuze has made some efforts in rehabilitating it. It is also quite an oddity in the history of philosophy. It has been neglected because its scientific metaphysics obviously seems arcane and twee to the modern world view. Moreover, and as Alain Badiou points out it does not really get a mention on Heidegger’s list in the history of philosophy. This is relevant given Heidegger's long shadow on the humanities. Badiou rightly sees this as somewhat suspect given that Lucretius presents a dynamic metaphysics which does not fit so easily with Heidegger’s history of the metaphysics of presence. Another oddity about this text is that it is an epic poem; one of the few great attempts to salve the difference between philosophy and poetry the sibling rivalry that Plato argued put them both forever in tension. With regard to second claim, and without wanting to downgrade modern science, Lucretius’ brand of stoic philosophy makes a metaphysical claim about the nature of reality in terms of Being qua Being. He was not doing science as we nowadays conceive it i.e. experiments, trial and error etc. Lucretius wants to present an ontology from first principles, one that gives expression to the place of human beings as effects of the the nature of the universe. The modern separation between the ontological and the ethical ala Kant was not an issue here. So what is it that merits reading Lucretius work? I think Lucretius is valuable as a materialist metaphysician, he presents a radically dynamic and strife ridden view of reality. There are only two things for Lucretius, Being and Void. Being is only the collision and contact of atoms in the Void or space. Everything that is the case comes from the inertia of the atomic collisions. This is to say, if there is an event, if something happens, there has to be a collision of indivisible and infinite atoms. While the atoms are small and of varying sizes, they are multiple and generate the events that we take to be real; objects in the world are thus only ever what they are because of their relationality and minimal contact with other objects. Highlights of De Rerum Natura for me would be the alleviation of human mortality in the face of death, also, stylistically Lucretius is up there with the great stylists in philosophy (he would be on a par for me with Nietzsche had he only written more works) Lucretius offers a viscous account of the nature of the universe, it is thick with the sensuality and sensuousness of material experience. Also, I admire the poetic unity of De Rerum Natura , it moves from life to death, from the most high to the most low; death and life are held in fine balance at all stages of existence as well of the cosmic relation of all Beings. In effect, Lucretius has one metaphysical principle that explains all things: that of Being and Void. There is a strange egalitarianism to this; everything from the most high to the lowest is a result of singular instances of the same principles. Thus the human is no more centre of the universe than sheep in a field, fish in the sea or scales on a fish. All of this and 1600 years before Galileo!!

Honourable mentions:
4. Tony Harrison: V. Bloodaxe: Newcastle-on-Tyne: 1989. Tony Harrison’s epic meditation on the letter 'V' presents an exceptional account of class war, internal and external and cultural tensions during the Miner’s Strike.
5. Philip Pullman, His Dark Materials. London: Scholastic Books, 2000-2007. Pullman’s trilogy is special. He sets himself the daunting task of asking how one has a soul in a materialist universe!
6. Ullrich Haase, Starting with Nietzsche, London: Continuum, 2008. This is a brilliant little book. The best and most imaginative introduction to Nietzsche you will find. Clear, concise and original; Haase presents you with an existential Nietzsche who’s ultimate concern is giving expression to our ‘historicity’. Mercifully, it forgoes the usual Nietzsche as proto-fascist and frustrated over man type of stuff.

Sunday, 13 December 2009

Neil's Top 100 Intellectuals

Dear everyone

Here's my attempt at compiling a list of the current top 100 intellectuals!! Do you agree with my listings? Have I overlooked anyone?



Noam Chomsky (Linguist, US, 72).
Jürgen Habermas (Social Theorist, German, 76)
Niklas Luhmann (Sociologist, German)
Karl Otto Apel (Philosopher, German)
Rem Koolhaas (Architect, Netherlands)
Umberto Eco (Semiotician, Italy)
Hayden White (Historian, US)
Philip Lacou-Labathe (Philosopher, France)
Robert Brandom (Philosopher, US)
Michael Dummett (Philosopher, UK)
Jean-Luc Marion (Theologian, US)
Regina Schwartz (Theorist, US)
Ian Hacking (Philosopher, UK)
Anthony Giddens (Social Theorist, UK)
Paul Rabinow (Anthroplogist/Theorist, US)
Manuel de Landa (Philosopher, US)
Serge Eisenstadt (Sociologist, Isreal)
Julia Kristeva (Philosopher/Theorist France/Bulgaria)
Luce Irigaray (Philosopher, Beligium)
Slavoj Zizek (Philosopher/Theorist, Slovenia)
Ulrich Beck (Sociologist, Germany)
Michael Hardt (Theorist, USA)
Antonio Negri (Political Theorist, Italy)
Richard Rorty (Philosopher, US)
Georgio Agamben (Philosopher, Italy)
G. Vattimo (Philosopher/Theorist, Italy)
Jean-Luc Nancy (Philosopher, France)
Jean Baudrillard (Theorist, France)
Jerome Bruner (Psychologist, US)
Bruno Latour (Social Theorist, France)
Stephen Shapin (Historian of Science, UK)
Nicholas Rose (Psychologist/Theorist UK)
Nancy Fraser (Social Theorist, US)
Richard Bernstein (Social Theorist, US)
Marshall Berman (Theorist, US)
Benedict Anderson (Social Theorist, UK)
Tom Nairn (Political Scientist, UK)
Charles Taylor (Philosopher, Canada)
Iris Marion Young (Political Theorist, US)
Stanley Cavell (Philosopher ,US)
Gaytri Chakrvorty Spivak (Theorist, India)
bell hooks (literary theorist, US)
Cornell West (philosopher, US)
Douglas Kellner (Theorist, US)
Frederick Jameson (Theorist US)
Carol Gilligan (Psychologist, US)
Theordore Roszack (Theorist US)
Helene Cixous (Theorist, France)
James Der Derian (Political Theorist, US)
Homi Bhabba (Theorist, UK)
Manuel Castells (Social Theorist, US)
David Harvey (Geographer, UK
Peter Berger (Sociologist, US)
Thomas Luckmann (Sociologist, US)
Alain Badiou (Philosopher, France)
Regis Debray (Theorist, France)
Sherry Turkle (Theorist, US)
M. Maffesoli (Social Theorist, France)
Marvin Minksy (Cognitive Scientist, US)
Seymour Papert (Cognitive Scientist, US)
Donna Haraway (Theorist, US)
John Searle (Philosopher, US)
Paul Gilroy (Theorist, UK)
Serge Moscovici (Psychologist, France)
Francis Fukuyama (Political Theorist, US)
Arthur Kroker (Theorist, US)
Daniel Bell (Sociologist, US)
Amartya Sen (Economist, US)
Joseph Sieglitz (Economist, US)
Bernard Stiegler (Theorist, France)
Daniel Dennett (Philosopher, US)
Paul Virilo (Social Theorist, France)
Hubert Dreyfus (Philosopher, US)
Zygmunt Bauman (Sociologist, UK)
Richard Kearney (Philosopher, Eire)
Martha Nussbaum (Political Theorist, US)
Andre Gorz (Political Theorist, France)
Paul Churchland (Cognitive Scientist, US)
Patricia Churchland (Cognitive Scientist, US)
Herbert Schiller (Political Theorist, US)
John Gray (Political Theorist, UK)
Saskia Sassen (Sociologist, US)
Stanley Fish (Philosopher, US)
Mike Davis (Geographer, US)
Richard Sennett (Sociologist, UK)
Judith Butler (Theorist, US)
Paul Rabinow (Anthroplogist, US)
Ernesto Laclau (Political Theorist, UK)
Chantal Mouffe (Political Theorist, Belgium)
Immanuel Wallestein (Political Theorist, US)

Neil Turnbull

Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius!

Born 480 in Rome into an aristocratic, Christian-Roman family, he was a statesman and a philosopher. He translated many of the Greek philosophers’ works into Latin and these translations remained in use during the middle ages. He became Consul before finally being imprisoned and then executed for treason in 524.

During his imprisonment, he wrote his most famous work, “De Consolatione Philosophiae” (The Consolation). This took the form of a conversation between Boethius and 'Lady Philosophy' in which she tries to console Boethius the fallen statesman. She does this by highlighting the transitory nature of all earthly splendour and greatness with the superior greatness of things of the mind and virtue. Although he was a Christian, this work bears no Christian references and draws from the Neo-Platonists and Stoics such as Seneca.

Neil Turnbull

Friday, 11 December 2009

Philosophy and Food

Just to remind you that philosophy can feed your
belly as well as your soul! Here are some famous, and relatively
famous people, who hold or held philosophy degrees.

Woody Allen -- Director and Comedian
Matt Groening --Creator of The Simpsons
Bruce Lee -- martial arts & actor
Stephen Colbert -- Comedien
John Chancellor -- News Broadcaster
Harrison Ford -- Actor
Chris Hardwick -- MTV Host
Jay Leno -- Comedian and Host The Tonight Show
Amy Madigan -- Actress
Steve Martin -- Comedian, Actor
Dennis Miller -- Comedian
Stone Phillips -- News Broadcaster
Brad Roberts -- Singer, songwriter Crash Test Dummies
Susan Sarandon -- Actress
Gene Siskel -- Movie Critic
Jeff Smith -- Frugal Gourmet
Steve Thomas -- Host for TV Show, This Old House
Alex Trebek -- Host for TV Show, Jeopardy
Mark Hulbert -- financial columnist FORBES magazine
Carl Icahn -- CEO, TWA Airlines
Gerald Levin -- CEO, Time-Warner, Inc.
George Soros -- Financier & Money Manager
Moses Znaimer -- Owner of CITY-TV and MUCH-MUSIC, Toronto
Gertrude Himmelfarb -- Historian
Herbert Simon -- Economist, and Nobel Laureate
William Bennett -- Secretary of Education and Head of the Drug Enforcement Agency
Patrick Buchanan -- Presidential Candidate and Political Columnist
Angela Davis -- Social Activist and Political Philosopher
Thomas Jefferson -- U.S. President
Vaclav Havel -- former President of Czeckoslovakia
Robert MacNamara -- Secretary of Defense and Head of the World Bank
David Souter -- Supreme Court Justice
Mary Higgins Clark -- Mystery Writer
Joseph Chaikin -- Theatre Director
Ethan Coen -- Film Maker
Umberto Eco -- Novelist and Semiologist
Ken Follett -- British Writer
Northrop Frye -- Literary Critic
Iris Murdoch -- Novelist
Alexander Solzhenitsin--Writer
Susan Sontag -- Writer
Martin Luther King, Jr -- Minister & Civil Rights Leader
Pope John Paul II -- Vicar of Christ
Phil Jackson -- Coach, Chicago Bulls
Michael McKaskey -- Owner, Chicago Bears
Aaron Taylor -- Offensive Tackle, Green Bay Packers
John Elway -- Quarterback, National Football League
Mike Schmidt -- former Philadelphia Philly
Beverly McLachlin -- Canadian Chief Justice
Ed Broadbent -- leader of Canada's federal NDP1970's and 1980's (Ph.D in philsophy)
Pierre Trudeau -- Former Canadian Prime Minister
Dave Thomas -- one of the "Mackenzie Brothers" on SCTV
Rick Salutin -- columnist for THE GLOBE AND MAIL
Steve Allen -- writer & comedian
David Duchovny -- actor on X-FILES
Kate Millett -- author of SEXUAL POLITICS
Patricia Rozema -- film-maker, I'VE HEARD THE MERMAIDS SINGING
Neil Peart -- drummer for rock group, RUSH
Susan Block -- Host, HBO's RADIO SEX TV, THE DR. SUSAN BLOCK SHOW on Radio, cable TV, and the internet

Patrick O'Connor

Thursday, 10 December 2009

Guest Lecture II: Is there anything that could not count as a moral issue?


Trevor Curnow, Reader in Philosophy from University of Cumbria came along to NTU on 9th Dec as part of the Philosophy and Everyday Life guest lecture series. In contrast to Neal Curtis’s session, Trevor offered us a technology free overview of moral philosophy in general and Ancient Philosophy in particular.

He delivered his lecture in traditional philosophical style by standing and delivering an entertaining, fluent, and at times digressive talk without recourse to technology of any kind (not even a pen!). By drawing upon, amongst other things, biographical details concerning his early philosophical training in analytical philosophy, (in particular what passed for moral philosophy in the 1970s), and contemporary philosophy’s issue based approach to ethics, Trevor demonstrated his overall thesis: that contemporary moral philosophy has been impoverished by its refusal to incorporate all aspects of everyday life as the Ancient Greeks did.


Moreover, Trevor suggested that this state of affairs has been exacerbated by the academicisation of philosophy and the consequent lack of philosophical role models, deploring a society which appears to be in thrall to celebrity culture and hysterically mourns a princess who had little relevance to most people’s lives.

In contrast, the Ancient Greek Schools offered philosophers as role models. For them, how one comports oneself in everyday life, whether alone or with others, constitutes the bedrock of one’s character. In this way, we constitute ourselves. It is only on death that a person can be judged to have lived a moral life or otherwise, when all of one’s actions can finally be accounted for.

In Trevor’s view, it is pointless to corral off “moral issues” when everyday existence itself is an ongoing ethical project. We are responsible for what we are and what we may become.

This approach to moral philosophy has practical consequences on the most mundane level. Ethical decisions pertain to the micro as well as macro levels. What one chooses to eat for breakfast, how long one spends in bed, for example, these are moral issues just as much as whether to commit suicide since, viewed in terms of the seven Deadly sins, gorging oneself on breakfast constitutes gluttony, while staying in bed all day becomes sloth.

Trevor is clearly a convert to the ethical ways of the Ancient Greeks, and his talk reflected this, managing to be simultaneously provocative and laconic. No ranting to be had here and all the better for it.

After all, if we accept that we are the sum total of our actions in everyday life, then that is a thought that has the potential to change the way we live. And philosophy doesn’t get much more relevant, or radical, than that.

Ruth Griffin